Skip to content
Scan a barcode
Scan
Hardcover An Investigation Of The Laws Of Thought, On Which Are Founded The Mathematical Theories Of Logic And Probabilities Book

ISBN: 1015416829

ISBN13: 9781015416826

An Investigation Of The Laws Of Thought, On Which Are Founded The Mathematical Theories Of Logic And Probabilities

Select Format

Select Condition ThriftBooks Help Icon

Recommended

Format: Hardcover

Condition: New

$38.95
50 Available
Ships within 2-3 days

Book Overview

This work has been selected by scholars as being culturally important, and is part of the knowledge base of civilization as we know it.

This work is in the "public domain in the United States of America, and possibly other nations. Within the United States, you may freely copy and distribute this work, as no entity (individual or corporate) has a copyright on the body of the work.

Scholars believe, and we concur, that this work is important...

Customer Reviews

5 ratings

Lucid reading

Descartes made a revolutionary move when he symbolized geometry with algebra and used the methods of algebra to solve geometrical problems. For example, he defined a line with y=mx+b. Similarly, Boole made a revolutionary move here when he symbolized logic with algebra and used the methods of algebra to solve logical problems. That is the whole gist of this book. In addition, Boole has an eloquent writing style.

This Edition Introduces Boole to a New Generation

Instead of writing an original review, I decided to quote excerpts from a review by Prof. James Van Evra, a noted authority on Boole and on the history of logic since 1800. The entire review can be found in the journal PHILOSOPHY IN REVIEW; Volume 24 (2004) pages 167-169. The words below are all by Prof. Van Evra. The body of this book is a replica of the 1854 edition of George Boole's great work in logic. While it has been widely available in this form for over a century, what sets this edition apart is the inclusion of John Corcoran's extensive and penetrating introduction both to the text and to Boole's logical thought more generally. The result is a valuable addition to Boole scholarship conveniently bound with Boole's major work. Corcoran's commentary is valuable to those already familiar with Boole's work, but is especially helpful to those approaching it for the first time. Many existing commentaries approach Boole from a present day perspective, i.e. as anticipating, however imperfectly, things to come (W. V. O. Quine's review of Desmond MacHale's biography of Boole ("In the Logical Vestibule") is an excellent example of this approach). There is some justification for doing this--Boole, after all, tended to be forward looking and had little positive to say about the tradition which preceded him. The effect of such an approach, however, is a tendency to stress what is lacking in Boole, rather than his positive contribution. Corcoran, by contrast, uses Aristotle's theory of logic as a baseline for his analysis. Starting with simple sentences and immediate inference, Corcoran clearly and accurately shows how Boole's logic covers the same ground. As he puts it, `Boole was one of the last logicians to take [the subject-connector-predicate view of simple propositions] seriously' (xiii). The result of Corcoran's approach is a view in which Boole's logic is seen to be simpler than Aristotle's in one respect (i.e. as a unified system), and more complicated in another (extending the range of propositions covered within it). By beginning with Aristotle, Corcoran's analysis provides an exceptionally clear account of Boole's positive contributions to logic. At the same time, Corcoran also describes things that Boole's system lacks. Thus he points out that Boole never recognized indirect inference, and he notes problems that arise when Boole attempts to use algebraic devices (such as solving equations) as a warrant for logical inference (not all algebraic operations result in logically valid inferences). By detailing both the strengths and weaknesses in Boole's theory, Corcoran provides a balanced and accurate account Boole's proper place in the modern development of logic. Another welcome feature of Corcoran's introduction is the inclusion of references, often to recent encyclopedia articles, at just those points at which readers with relatively little technical background encounter concepts that require some further explanation. Such an addition mak

Boole's LT Breaks Ancient Mold , Founds Math Logic

. Aristotle and Boole are the two most original logicians before the era of modern logic. Aristotle presented the world's first system of logic. His system involves the standard three parts: first, a limited formalized predicational language; second, a formal method of step-by-step deductions for establishing validity of arguments having unlimited numbers of premisses; and third, an equally general method of countermodels for establishing invalidity. Boole's LAWS OF THOUGHT showed that logic is mathematical. Its stated aims were to refine, systematize, and complete the project started by Aristotle and, more ambitiously, to demonstrate the mathematical character of logic. His two-part system involves, first, a limited formalized equational language capable of expressing tautologies or "laws of thought", a breakthrough dramatically altering Aristotle's plan, and, second, a semi-formal method of derivation using equational reasoning totally absent from previous systematic logic. Boole's primary goals included construction of a method for generating solutions to sets of equations regarded as conditions on "unknowns", an unprecedented innovation with radical implications for the future development of logic. As for the third part of a system of logic, a method of establishing invalidity, surprisingly, Boole's book contains no systematic discussion of independence nor does it contain anything like a method of countermodels. Boole's LAWS OF THOUGHT set in motion forces that would lead to the ultimate fulfillment many of his goals including the establishment of mathematical logic.

NOW IS A GOOD TIME TO STUDY BOOLE.

The publication of The Laws of Thought in 1854 launched modern mathematical logic. The author George Boole (1815-1864) was already a celebrated mathematician specializing in what is known as analysis. If, as Aristotle (384-322 B.C.E.) tells us, we do not understand a thing until we see it growing from its beginning, then those who want to understand modern mathematical logic should begin with The Laws of Thought. There are many wonderful things about this book besides its historical importance. For one thing, the reader does not need to know any mathematical logic. There was none available to the audience for which it was written-even today a little basic algebra and a semester's worth of beginning logic is all that is required. For another thing, the book is exciting reading. The reader comes to feel through Boole's intense, serious, and sometimes labored writing that the birth of something very important is being witnessed. Of all the foundational writings concerning mathematical logic, this one is the most accessible to the nonexpert and it has the most to offer the nonexpert. The secondary literature on Boole is lively and growing, as can be seen from an excellent recent anthology (A BOOLE ANTHOLOGY by J.Gasser 2000) and a complete bibliography that is now available (Nambiar 2003). Boole's manuscripts on logic and philosophy, once nearly inaccessible, are now in print (Grattan-Guinness and Bornet 1997). This is a good time to start to study Boole.It is true that Boole had written on logic before, but his earlier work did not attract much attention until after his reputation as a logician was established. Today he is known almost exclusively for his logic. In 1848 he published a short paper "The Calculus of Logic" (Boole 1848) and in 1847, at his own expense, he published a pamphlet The Mathematical Analysis of Logic (Boole1847). By the expression `mathematical analysis of logic' Boole did not mean to suggest that he was analyzing logic mathematically or that he was using mathematics to analyze logic. Rather his meaning was that he had found logic to be a new form of mathematics, not a form of philosophy as had been previously thought. More specifically, his point was that he had found logic to be a form of the branch of mathematics known as mathematical analysis, which includes algebra and calculus. (For a short description of this branch of mathematics, see the article "Mathematical Analysis" in the 1999 Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy (Audi 1999, 540-41).Although this book begins mathematical logic, it does not begin logical theory. The construction of logical theory begins, of course, with Aristotle whose logical writings were known and admired by Boole. In fact, Boole explicitly accepted Aristotle's logic as "a collection of scientific truths" (1854, 241) and he regarded himself as following in Aristotle's footsteps. He thought that he was supplying a unifying foundation for Aristotle's logic and that he was at the same time expandi

difficult, but a classic--and worth the effort.

Yes, this is the Boole of Boolean algebra. No, this is not a primer. But if you have any interest at all in intellectual history or where the tools of computer science came from, then you will find this book worth the effort.
Copyright © 2024 Thriftbooks.com Terms of Use | Privacy Policy | Do Not Sell/Share My Personal Information | Cookie Policy | Cookie Preferences | Accessibility Statement
ThriftBooks® and the ThriftBooks® logo are registered trademarks of Thrift Books Global, LLC
GoDaddy Verified and Secured